ࡱ> Root Entry F<)1TableWordDocumentSummaryInformation( y  !"#$%&'()*+,-./0123456789:;<=>?@ABCDEFGHIJKLMNOPQRSTUVWXYZ[\]^_`abcdefghijklmnopqrstuvwxyz{|}~r4@B4Header  !OJQJDR`RDBody Text Indent 2 $\4B`b4 Body Text $dEH(DS"#%FJJK'LN]hchyiKmov݂  6b)S T | 2p Root Entry F1*1TableWordDocumentSummaryInformation(   !"#$%&'()*+,-./0123456789:;<=>?@ABCDEFGHIJKLMNOPQRSTUVWXYZ[\]^_`abcdefghijklmnopqrstuvwxyz{|}~$dOJQJ&)@1& Page Number4@B4Header  !OJQJDR`RDBody Text Indent 2 $\4B`b4 Body Text $dEH(DS"#%FJJK'LN]hchyiKmov݂ 6b)S T | 2pmzB(NormalCJmH @@@ Heading 1$$@& 5OJQJ<A@<Default Paragraph Font8>@8Title$d 5OJQJ8&@8Footnote ReferenceH*:@: Footnote Text CJOJQJJC@"JBody Text Indent$dOJQJ&)@1& Page Number4@B4Header rstanding foundational problems in biology through a study of the historical origins and development of those problems. I will label this approach the phylogenetic approach to the philosophy of science. This label is intended to highlight the analogy between this approach to the philosophy of science and the way in which evolutionary biologists use phylogenetic reconstruction to understand current organisms. I will begin with a somewhat crude and impressionistic outline of what I have in mind by that phrase, turn to a detailed example, and close with a less crude and more realist account. 2. The phylogeny of foundational problems. To begin with, we need an account of what sorts of things a philosopher of science can do. Here I am an unabashed technicalist. The philosopher of science focuses a particular kind of training and expertise on puzzles, paradoxes and confusions in the foundations of science generally, and of special sciences specifically. Whether it is puzzles about quantum non-locality, singularities in relativity theory, group selection and fitness in evolutionary theory, or information theory in thermodynamics, there is a place for people trained to look for the hidden presuppositions of different approaches, or for their logical virtues and flaws, or to draw out imaginatively the consequences of different ways of conceptualizing or formulating a theory or problem. Similarly, there may be unusual or problematic approaches to testing, confirming and rejecting hypotheses in the sciences that may benefit from philosophical scrutiny. But for such scrutiny to be of value, philosophers must know what those problems are, and know them in the form they take in the actual sciences. But so conceptualized, why would philosophy of science have any need for the history of science? The answer lies, I believe, in the fact that the foundations of a particular scientific field are shaped by its history, and to a much greater degree than many of the practitioners of a science realize. There is more conceptual freedom in the way theories--even richly confirmed theories--may be formulated and revised than is usually realized. Studying the way they actually came to be formulated and revised historically can be of considerable value in do philosophical work. My primary argument for this claim will be by means of compelling instantiation, but the idea can be given initial plausibility by considering two well-known episodes in biologys history. [i] It is well known that Charles Darwin was forced to present a cobbled-together sketch of his theory to the Linnaean Society in 1858 because he had received a paper by mail from Alfred Russel Wallace which, the myth goes, presented the same theory he had come up with 20 years earlier. This is a twofold myth: first, because their theories are, in fact, quite different; and second, because Darwins theory circa 1858 was significantly different from his theory circa 1838. Focusing only on the first myth: Wallaces theory has no place for the concept of natural selection; in fact, unlike Darwin, Wallace thinks that what occurs in domestic breeding would lead you to deny evolution, and is at great pains to indicate that natural populations are very different from domestic ones, and it is precisely those differences that allow them to evolve. Indeed he and a number of other of Darwins supporters regularly urged Darwin to cast the metaphorical notion of natural selection, with its built in analogy to domestic selection, aside. Furthermore, Wallaces theory lacks a mechanism of speciation, Darwins central concern. The presence within a species of a typical form and occasional varieties is taken for granted. The struggle for existence leads to the gradual replacement of the typical form by the variety. The following passage will give you the feel for Wallaces approach: The variety would now have replaced the species, of which it would be a more perfectly developed and more highly organized form. It would be in all respects better adapted to secure its safety, and to prolong its individual existence and that of the race. Such a variety could not return to the original form; for that form is an inferior one, and could never compete with it for existence. (Wallace 1859, 58; emphasis in original) It is not hard to imagine a scenario whereby Wallaces version of evolutionary theory prevails. Had that happened, the conceptual and logical foundations of evolutionary biology would have gotten off to a different start and moved along a different conceptual trajectory. [ii] It is likewise well-known that Gregor Mendel published the lectures presenting his experiments with hybrid pea-plants in a new Society Proceedings that was then fairly widely distributed around Europe; and that his work received very little notice, being occasionally reported without fanfare in surveys of hybridization research, but otherwise ignored. In 1900, the story goes, three researchers (C. Correns, H. De Vries, E. Tschermak) published the results of their research with hybrids from different genera, each of them noting the same F2 3:1 (or 1:2:1) ratios and all citing Mendels earlier work. But again the myth covers up the different theoretical and methodological approaches of these re-discoverers, as well as their differences with Mendel--different experimental methods, different mathematical techniques, different theoretical pre-suppositions and conclusions drawn. In this case the history is remarkably complicated, and the methodological, mathematical, and conceptual foundations of modern genetics owes a great deal to its radically contingent history. This by itself does not make the history of science of central importance to the philosophy of science. However, among the historical contingencies built into the theories, methods, and explanatory techniques of a science are those that lead to theoretical and methodological problems for that science. Under such circumstances, a careful examination of that sciences historical trajectory is crucial in providing various sorts of help toward philosophical understanding. Let me say a bit more about two sorts of help historical investigation can provide. 1. Alternatives. A reasonably mature science is the result of a number of decisions made, at various historical nodes, among a variety of possible options ought to be taken. As one traces back through the history of a current theory, one finds various alternatives. This historical research opens up a space of theoretical possibilities that were earlier rejected, or not considered, but in the light of current problems, may seem interesting. Stephen J. Gould often mines the history of science in search of alternatives to neo-Darwinism, for example. His claims about the hardening of the Neo-darwinian synthesis are claims that a variety of theoretical options available for exploration in the early work of people like Sewall Wright and George G. Simpson were simply not pursued. Why werent they? Should they have been? Would those options help us with some of the foundational problems in evolutionary biology today? These are historical questions with philosophical pay-offs. 2. Locating the Source of the Problem. Certain problems in the philosophy of biology, as I will demonstrate, have an historical origin. Go back to, say, 1875, and evolutionary theory lacked various problems it now faces--and had many it now lacks! By moving forward in time, it may be possible to focus in on the theoretical developments that set the scene for the problems that now concern us. Prior to doing such historical work, the problem may seem intractable, hard to understand, even paradoxical. Seeing the problem gradually emerge and become explicitly recognized as a problem helps theoreticians and philosophers, I believe, to understand it. I have called this a phylogenetic approach to the philosophy of science. I would now like to exploit the evolutionary metaphor from which that name comes to further explicate the basic idea here. Some of the most compelling evidence of the evolutionary history of an organism comes from features it possesses that are [i] widely shared with organisms in very different environments and/or [ii] of little or no adaptive value in that organisms current environment. We easily think of vestigial structures such as the subcutaneous eyes of moles or hind limb skeletal remnants of cetaceans in this way. But organisms are mostly their deep history, rather than their recent adaptations. There are no doubt endless numbers of better designed skeletons for upright locomotion than ours--ours reflects an endless variety of changing conditions imposed on us throughout our evolutionary history. The evolutionary trajectory of a particular contemporary species is inscribed in its genotype and displayed in its phenotype. Natural selection tinkers with what history provides, but it seldom does more. Local, highly contingent adaptations get built in to the genetic heritage of a species, and further adaptation is a modification of that heritage. So with our current scientific theories--the modifications and revisions they constantly undergo are highly constrained by their historical baggage. But that history was not aiming toward the current version of the theory (thus this historiographic approach avoids the label, Whig), and it is not linear. Like evolutionary phylogenies, in the branching network of science there are likely to have been a variety of developments going off in different directions from any particular node, many of which became dead ends, some of which did not, and perhaps one of which comes to be the dominant or received theoretical approach (as with the Neo-darwinian synthesis in the 1940s and 50s). What constraints operate such that certain branches develop and others do not? First and foremost are the empirical constraints. A significant part of what makes one revised version of a theory last and come to dominate is its superior ability to resolve empirical anomalies, to suggest novel tests, ideally tests that force choices among competitors, to account for evidence formerly not thought of as evidence for that theory at all, and so on. I would argue that, while this is not the only environmental factor shaping theory construction and revision, it is the most important one in the historical sequences I have studied. Having said that, it would be hard to find an episode in the history of science in which some features, even some important features, of the theory were not adopted for reasons other than judgments of empirical adequacy. As I will argue shortly, the so-called tautology problem in Darwinian selection theory, which philosophers have played a central role in helping resolve, emerged as a consequence of a series of fundamental conceptual and methodological changes in the theory of evolution by natural selection. It is arguable that none of those changes was mandated by empirical considerations. I dont want to claim that empirical considerations played no role--only that, whatever role they played, it was far short of determinative of the historical trajectory of the theory. 3. A Case in Point: Fitness, Adaptation and Explanation One of the problematic features of the phylogenetic approach to philosophy of science is that it starts with a philosophical problem at a certain point in a theorys development, and looks back to history with this problem in mind. From a historians point of view, nothing could be more suspect. I have denied that the method I am advocating is Whiggish, but can one use such an approach and truly avoid that label? Using a detailed case study, I hope to show that one can. The problem I shall focus on is one that has been badly misunderstood, by Karl Popper and others, misunderstandings exploited by scientific creationists and their fellow travelers. But it is a real problem, and we need to begin by formulating it. In contemporary population genetics, the mechanics of evolutionary theory as Richard Lewontin has called it, the concepts of mean fitness and selection coefficient play a key role. Both claim to be represented by mathematical variables in the mathematical models of the theory. Applying the modelsi.e. solving the equations--requires supplying values for these variables based on different possible gene combinations at a given locus. Those values are derived from statistical samplings of populations over a number of generations. The wrongly labeled tautology problem arises from the fact that these relative fitness values are apparently determined by sampling actual populations to determine the actual relative reproductive rates of the different phenotypes. Judgments of relative fitness are based on the actual relative increases and decreases in the frequencies of the allelic combinations under consideration. But it is these changes in relative frequencies that the models are supposed to explain. And they can only do this if the fitness of a genotype represents something about it that explains these changes in its relative frequency. If it does not, then these models are explanatorily sterile. Now there is a quick answer to this problem that unfortunately does not work. One simply says that the way the theory works, one predicts certain changes in relative frequencies based on engineering, optimal design or life history considerations, and then tests it by doing population studies (for the moment whether tightly controlled laboratory studies or random sampling of wild populations is not at issue). There is a more and a less fundamental problem with this quick answer. The less fundamental problem is that it is completely unclear how one uses this sort of analysis to derive specific, quantifiable fitness values. If one is simply using guess work, this approach quickly degenerates into the aforementioned sterility--in practice one just keeps adjusting the values until they come within tolerable limits of the values actually found. The more fundamental problem is that we no longer have a single theory, but a potentially infinite number of ad hoc models. After all, the gene combinations that make a horseshoe crab, a scarab beetle, a Caribbean guppy, and an African bonobo well-adapted to their environments are utterly different, but the fitness value of some allele relevant to their adaptedness may be exactly the same. A variety of solutions to this worry have been proposed, and it is not (fortunately) my task today to adjudicate between them. Some have suggested that fitness be conceived as a reproductive propensity, which given that the mathematical notion of fitness is clearly probabilistic, makes sense. Others have suggested that it is a property that supervenes on an endless variety of different adaptive arrays. Still others have suggested that it be considered as an uninterpreted term of the theory, which takes on empirical content only in its explanatory applications. Finally Lindley Darden and Joe Cain, and independently Bradley Wilson and I, have suggested that it be viewed as an middle range abstraction. What I want to outline today is the way in which studying the history of this subject provides one with a space of philosophical alternatives to the theoretical approach that generates the problem and with a deeper understanding of it. If we return to Charles Darwins Darwinism, we can see that the theory of evolution by natural selection is free of this problem, but for suspect reasons. Darwin made no attempt at all to investigate populations empirically to see whether the mechanisms described in the first four chapters of On the Origin of Species actually produce differential changes in the frequencies of small heritable variations, as he claims they will. It is unclear why he does not do this, but two reasons are suggested by other aspects of his theoretical perspective. Darwin seemed to think that selection-driven evolution moves with unimaginable slowness in nature--he may thus have assumed that direct evidence would never be available. It is sometimes (wrongly) claimed that he thought that evidence of domestic or artificial selection was sufficient to support his theory. It is clear from the following remark, concluding the chapters that presented his theory, that he did not think that. Whether natural selection has really thus acted in nature, in modifying and adapting the various forms of life to their several conditions and stations, must be judged of by the general tenour and balance of evidence given in the following chapters. (Darwin 1859, 127) Another possible reason for his not attempting to investigate selection in natural populations is suggested by his theorys most obvious shortcoming, its lack of an account of the origins of variation and of the mechanisms of inheritance. Without a method for disentangling the heritable and non-heritable components of variation in a population, such an investigation would have been futile--and Darwin was acutely aware that he had no method for doing this. At any rate, Darwin and his followers were well aware that the theory was untestable without a well-verified mechanism of inheritance, since it was by the differential passing on of traits from one generation to the next that evolutionary change was alleged, on his theory, to take place. One central project for biology between 1880 and 1920 was to nail down such a mechanism, and to figure out how to apply information learned in highly controlled experimental settings (such as hybrid breeding experiments) to natural, uncontrolled populations. The form of genetics that caught on was Mendelian, which used simple statistics and probability theory to analyze the results of experiments involving hybrid crosses, self-fertilization of hybrids and back-crosses of hybrids with pure lines, and to make inferences about the cellular mechanisms producing the resulting ratios of observed traits. This, combined with the increasing power of the light microscope to observe meiosis and gametogenesis at the cellular level--including the behavior of chromosomes--provided biology with a powerful theory of the mechanisms of inheritance which included a clear method of experimentally testing theories and a clear connection between the phenotypic ratios to be explained and the genetic mechanism doing the explaining. But how to apply this theory to nature? Well, as it turned out, a German Doctor named Weinberg and an English mathematician and cricket lover named Hardy provided a solution, which is incredibly simple. In response to a casual question put to him during a cricket match by the experimentalist R.C. Punnett, the mathematician G.H. Hardy pointed out that Mendel's laws, derived from the crossing of pure lines followed by repeated self-fertilization of the resulting hybrids, could be generalized to apply to large randomly breeding populations. Mendel's insights into 'the laws governing the distributions of characters in hybrids' can be transformed into a formula representing the ratio of different genetic makeups (termed genotypes) in a population formed by the random mating of individuals with different forms of the same gene. If we represent the different forms of the gene at the same locus (known as different alleles) by A and a respectively, that formula will look like this: AA: 2Aa: aa The frequencies of the different genotypes can then be represented as follows: p2+2pq+q2=1 where p=the frequency of A, q=the frequency of a, and p+q=1. The Hardy-Weinberg Law thus gives us a 'base line' with which we can compare actual changes in frequencies of alleles across generations of reproductive communities. Deviations from this base line indicate a disruption of this equilibrium of genotypic frequencies across generations. There are a number of factors that may lead to such disruptions: a variety of forms of alteration of the genetic material (mutation), the migration of new genes into the population (which will change the initial frequencies), random changes in frequencies arising from sampling error (known as genetic drift) and selection favoring one genotype over another. Assuming other disruptive forces have been corrected for or ruled out, population genetics builds into its models the notion that a change in the frequency of a particular genotype is a measure of its relative fitness . This was a fundamental assumption of the genetical theory of natural selection developed by Ronald Fisher in a book by that name. Again, I dont have time to tell even the outlines of the story, but that theory was quickly and vigorously attacked in a brilliant review by an American theoretician who had been developing an entirely different approach to the same problem--different models, different mathematics, different assumptions about typical natural populations. His name was Sewall Wright. One can think of the relationship between these two brilliant thinkers in the following way: they were studying the same problem, they accepted the theory of the gene, they both saw the problem as a mathematical one, and yet they rejected each others basic assumptions. Fisher Wright 1. Virtually infinite populations 1. Small relatively isolated populations 2. Random mating 2. Sortative Mating 3. Differential changes 3. Differential changes due to a balance due to selection of four primary factors 4. Panadaptationism 4. Differences between populations seldom adaptational Partly because of the intense criticism and rivalry between these two men, both were keenly aware of their assumptions. Fisher had been trained as a mathematician and physicist--in a recent history of evolutionary biology, he is described as importing into evolutionary biology models taken from statistical mechanics and thermodynamics and as track[ing] the trajectories of genes in the same probabilistic spirit in which Maxwell, Boltzmann, and Gibbs tracked arrays of gas molecules. But Fisher was well aware of the dangers. After noting some remarkable resemblances between his fundamental theorem of natural selection and the second law of thermodynamics, he notes five profound differences between them, the second of which is worth quoting. Fitness, although measured by a uniform method, is qualitatively different for every different organism, whereas entropy, like temperature, is taken to have the same meaning for all physical systems. (Fisher 1930/58, 39-40) Alas, whether or not Fisher was the last population geneticist to make this point, it was quickly forgotten. For example, it is not uncommon today to see the general theory of natural selection stated in the following way. Most people are familiar with the basic theory of natural selection. Organisms vary in a heritable fashion; some variants leave more offspring than others; their characteristics, therefore, are represented at a greater frequency in the next generation. In this description of the theory of natural selection, the only explanation offered for the greater frequency of certain characteristics in the off-spring population than in the parent population is that the parents with those characteristics leave more off-spring. But that is a completely trivial result, and leaves environment/organism interactions (i.e. actual selection pressures) completely out of the equation. Darwinian Fitness often receives a similar treatment. Take, for example, the following glossary entry for 'Fitness' in a highly regarded primer in population genetics: Fitness: The reproductive contribution of an organism or genotype to the following generations. As an account of how one measures fitness differences in a population, this is completely innocuous. But, as Ronald Fisher said, fitness, although measured by a uniform method, is qualitatively different for every different organism... . Even then, as Sewall Wright would point out, that is only a measure of fitness if one assumes all the other factors that can effect reproductive rates can be ignored. There is clearly a conceptual muddle here. The concepts at the core of Darwinian selection theory have been operationalized, without the scientists who are doing so being aware of it. But if one goes back to the debate between Fisher and Wright, at the point at which this problem begins to emerge, one can begin to see what happened. The story of the emergence of this problem is remarkably complicated. There is clearly a political and value component to it, which Diane Paul, in her brief note on the history of the concept of fitness in Keywords in Evolutionary Biology, nicely illustrates by the following quote from the widely used textbook Principles of Genetics, co-authored by Sinnot, Dunn and Dobzhansky. These [struggle for existence, survival of the fittest] emotionally loaded phrases have been often misused for political propaganda purposes. A less spectacular but more accurate statement is that carriers of different genotypes transmit their genes to the succeeding generations at different rates... The fittest is nothing more remarkable than the producer of the greatest number of children and grandchildren (Sinnot et al., 1958, 100-101) Professor Paul trenchantly comments, Thus was born the famous tautology problem, which has bedeviled the field ever since.  Yet, as we have seen, there is another, very different, dimension to this history, which is highlighted by Fishers comment about the dis-analogy between his Principle of Natural Selection and the second law of thermodynamics, above. This dimension of the history tracks the introduction of mathematical model into the domain of evolutionary population dynamics. Suppose statistical studies of populations of morning glories and giraffes result in the discovery that the suite of genes for a particular coat pattern in the giraffes and for a certain color pattern in the flowers have exactly same mean fitness (say .65). What can this mean other than that they have the same relative rate of reproductive success? Neither their genotypes nor their phenotypes are the same. Their environments are entirely different, and the environmental variables relevant to differential rates of reproductive success between different genotypes are almost certainly going to be different. Yet if one is seeking a completely general mathematical model of fitness of the sort Fisher dreamed of, these differences must somehow be suppressed. Viewed from this vantage-point, t is hard to see how to avoid this problem. There is no doubt that, whether your bte noire was laissez-faire capitalism or fascism, if you imagined that survival of the fittest was popularly associated with either one, you would happily embrace a way of talking about fitness that de-coupled in from Darwins struggle for existence. But the de-coupling was, I think, also driven--perhaps primarily driven--by two quite different philosophical goals. The first of these goals was to be able to formulate this part of evolutionary biology in a recognizable mathematical formalism. The second, related, goal was to operationally define the key terms in the theory in a way that made it a completely general biological theory. Fisher, at least, was aware of the problems created by attempting to achieve this goal. Fitness is not, as the mathematical models make it appear to be, a single variable, different values of which belong to different genotypes. There is yet another problem with the approach initiated by Fisher. As Sewall Wright carefully described and illustrated (the third point of difference between him and Fisher noted above), there are a variety of factors that can be operative within a population leading to long term increases and decreases in the frequencies of genotypes in populations. Since this effect can be produced by mechanisms other than natural selection, and also can be absent because of a balance between selection and other forces (or even countervailing selection forces), it is unwise to assume that such an observed effect is the result of natural selection, or that its absence signals an absence of selection. Looking through John Endlers Natural Selection in the Wild, many of the methods he identifies as methods for detecting the operation of selection cannot distinguish among the various possible causes of differential reproductive rates. The theory of natural selection thus has two distinct philosophical problems: [1] The problem of Abstractness. Formulated as a quasi-mathematical theory, its variables seem not to represent any single varying property in nature. The traits of organisms and conditions of environments that concretely interact to bring about differential reproductive rates within populations seem impossible to represent in a single, abstract theory. [2] The problem of Differentiation. Even could we solve the problem of Abstractness, and formulate a concept of Fitness or Adaptedness that would unambiguously refer across all organic populations, there is a problem of how one differentiates changes in populations due to selection from the same changes produced by other mechanisms. The Phylogenetic Analysis of a Philosophical Problem In the last section I provided a small bit of a much more complex history, not as an end in itself, but as an example of how a phylogenetic analysis of a current problem in the foundations of evolutionary biology can help clarify the problem for philosophical purposes. The method I have used is to trace back historically to a point where the problem does not exist, and then work forward historically until one can see it beginning to emerge. As in this case, it is often true that at that point, those involved in the scientific debate will be quite self-conscious of problems that a couple of generations later are submerged as unquestioned, unanalyzed presuppositions of the fields common set of concepts and methods. People see the problems, but cannot see what it is about what they are doing that is producing the problems. Nor, while working with those concepts and methods can they imagine any other way of approaching their subject that will avoid the problems they are facing. What I hope is now clear is that foundational problems in the sciences--both of a methodological and conceptual kind-- arise in part because of a series of contingent choices (evolutionary novelties, if you like) about theory development and conceptualization made at various nodes of the phylogenetic history of that science. A careful study of the historical genealogy of a philosophical problem can provide a deeper understanding of it, and a richer sense of the theoretical alternatives open to us in solving it. I dont mean to suggest that this is the only worthwhile method for working on problems in the philosophy of science. What I hope I have convinced you of is that virtually every problem we work on in the philosophy of science can be illuminated by a phylogenetic reconstruction of that problem.  L. Laudan, Progress and its Problems, Berkeley 1977; R. Burian, More than a Marriage of Convenience: On the Inextricability of History and Philosophy of Science, Philosophy of Science 44 (1977) 1-42; R. Giere, History and Philosophy of Science: Intimate Relationship or Marriage of Convenience?, British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 24 (1973) 282-297; I. Lakatos, History of Science and its Rational Reconstructions, in Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science VIII, Dordrecht, 1971; S. Toulmin, Human Understanding , Vol. I, Princeton, 1972 .  See his Explaining Science, Chicago 1988.  The very question that Giere 1973 began with, in fact.  A fine survey of the actual history of the interactions between Darwin and Wallace before and after 1858 is available in M. J. Kottler, Charles Darwin and Alfred Russel Wallace: Two Decades of Debate over Natural Selection, in D. Kohn, ed., The Darwinian Heritage, Princeton 1985 , 327-366. However even Kottler underestimates the differences in the theories presented side by side in 1858.  The two 1858 papers, along with the introductory remarks of Charles Lyell and Joseph Dalton Hooker, can be seen in P. H. Barrett, ed., The Collected Papers of Charles Darwin, Chicago 1977.  Versuche ber Pflanzen-Hybriden, Verhandlungen des naturforschenden Vereines in Brnn , 4 (1865) 3-47.  English translations of the papers of De Vries and Correns can be found in C. Stern and E. R. Sherwood, eds., The Origins of Genetics: A Mendel Source Book, San Francisco 1966, 107-132; a tanslation of E. Tschermaks ber kntstliche Kreuzung bei Pisum sativum can be found in a special edition of the journal Genetics (The Birth of Genetics, Genetics 35, no. 5, pt. 2 (1950) 42-47.  R. Burian, Adaptationin M. Grene, ed., Dimensions of Darwinism, Cambridge, 1985, 287-314 :S. Mills and J. Beatty, The Propensity Interpretation of Fitness, Philosophy of Science 46 (1979) 263-286; R. Brandon, Adaptation and Environment, Princeton 1990.  See note 2.  A. Rosenberg, The Supervenience of Biological Concepts, Philosophy of Science 45 (1978) 368-386.  A. Rosenberg, Instrumental Biology or the Disunity of Science, Chicago 1993, 118-128.  L. Darden and J. Cain, Selection Type Theories, Philosophy of Science 56 (1989) 106-129 1990; J. Lennox and B. Wilson, Natural Selection and the Struggle for Existence, Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Vol. 25 (1994) No. 1, 65-80.  These comments build on J. G. Lennox, Darwinian Thought Experiments: A Function for Just-So Stories, in T. Horowitz and G. Massey, eds., Thought Experiments in Science and Philosophy, Savage MD, 1991, 223-246. The founding document is an apparently modest attempt on the part of a mathematician to correct an error made by a biologist about the implications of Mendel's laws for 'mixed' populations. Cf. G.H. Hardy, 'Mendelian Proportions in a Mixed Population', Science Vol. 28 [1908] 49-50; repr. in Peters 1959 60-61.  For simplicity I assume a locus with two alleles.  Ronald Fisher, The Genetical Theory of Natural Selection, Oxford 1930; 2nd. ed. 1958.  A fine discussion of their differences and rivalry can be found in W. Provine, Sewall Wright and Evolutionary Biology, Chicago, 1986, chs. 7-9.  Cf David J. Depew and Bruce H.Weber, Darwinism Evolving, Cambridge MA, 1995, 244.  David Sloan Wilson, The Natural Selection of Populations and Communities, Menlo Park 1980, 14.  F. A. Ayala, Population Genetics: A Primer, San Francisco, 1982, 240.  D. Paul, Fitness: Historical Considerations, in E. Fox Keller and E. Lloyd, eds., Keywords in Evolutionary Biology, Cambridge MA, 1992, 114).  Cf. J. Endler, Natural Selection in the Wild, Princeton 1986. PAGE 1 PAGE 26 ;.:Y X ELipR [ ""l$m$&&(((f,,..h1n167';+;;;"<_<BB.C5CCCDD EEEEdFpFGGIIJJHJRJJJJJ)K*KKKMMXN5>*6CJCJ j0JU65\;<}: Y@A " " $d$d $d$dd$d;<}: Y@A " "p$L&(/)b,c,./36 9"<#<^<_<?>9?WADbGH|yv<Ge_?@{| ;<oR.]^Ed- "p$L&(/)b,c,./36 9"<#<^<_<?>9?WADbGHKLNPPQ $d$dHKLNPPQQ^SXj\{\\]A])acccdGddeehhhhiijjl(m)mmmbop2rssrtu/y||yvo,l<uvÙęŚƚWߠu]ԧ#4@˵-     6bbb))S | | | 2p     6bbb)S T | | 2pj  L!L!!!!!!!!! ! ! ! ! !!!!!!!!!!!!!    4 #'L.G4:?E`KAPU\a3fj_nsVxe~%͏H͛ dMA<     o=InQ3;<}bc 12u |!}!#%'(++.0G46z9<<<<>?AnDG\I)LMEOPPRRS Y_jc/f0f1f2f3fFfffg,g-gggjjjkkkLlMlNmOmnooppq)stdvevvVx{7߂- ͏M͛7 !!!!!!!!zY!iY!!iY!!wH!&'!b!!ӤU!@A!!ӤU! !!&'! - ! !!34!~&!.!!G8!!J;!!ӤU!< .!34!@A!!!!&'!!,!34!|D@!>" !<9!G!,!>" !@m!!@m!Ӳ!f!z!M!<9!@m!@m!@m!@m!@m!@m!@m!6!6!@m!6!@m!<9!@m!!@m!G!@m!!@m!>" ! !@m! !@m!>" !!>" !,!@m! !>" !|D@!F!F!@m!>" !>" !@m!@m!@m!M!9Am!~&!i3!|D@!G!!@m!,!|D@!@m!!!!!;<}bc 12u |!}!#%'(++.0G46z9<<<<>?AnDG\I)LMEOPPRRS Y_jc/f0f1f2f3fFfffg,g-gggjjjkkkLlMlNmOmnooppq)stdvevvVx{7߂- ͏M͛7c*TץܨU}23qҰӰ  @ XN܀zh| "QlĊh^h|H|Unknown Center for Philosophy of Science james lennox !!  [ b *344=$= F !@@ Heading 1$$@& 5OJQJ<A@<Default Paragraph Font8>@8Title$d 5OJQJ8&@8Footnote ReferenceH*:@: Footnote Text CJOJQJJC@"JBody Text Indent$dOJQJ&)@1& Page Number4@B4Header  !OJQJDR`RDB [(@(NormalCJmH @@@ Heading 1$$@& 5OJQJ<A@<Default Paragraph Font8>@8Title$d 5OJQJ8&@8Footnote ReferenceH*:@: Footnote Text CJOJQJJC@"JBody Text Indent$dOJQJ&)@1& Page Number4@B4Header  !OJQJDR`RDBody Text Indent 2 $\4B`b4 Body Text $dEH(DS"#%FJJK'LN]hchyiKmov݂ 6b)S T | 2p  !!!##$#)#.#7###v$|$))k*t***++0015@55566%>->?@5I@I/K<B@S@DFHHKKNAOaWY YTYfZ[\\`bbbIfkfgg0gXghhMvOvx2ya{n{||1M} ͏̛6:06()=Däac5; 135oq Center for Philosophy of Science-Macintosh HD:Desktop Folder:HPS/Phylo to work Center for Philosophy of Science/Macintosh HD:Temporary Items:Word Work File A 1 Center for Philosophy of Science/Macintosh HD:Temporary Items:Word Work File A 1 Center for Philosophy of Science/Macintosh HD:Temporary Items:Word Work File A 1 Center for Philosophy of Science-Macintosh HD:Desktop Folder:HPS/Phylo to work james lennoxAMacintosh HD:Desktop Folder:blackwell/princeton:HPS Phylo to work james lennox2Macintosh HD:blackwell/princeton:HPS Phylo to work james lennox2Macintosh HD:blackwell/princeton:HPS Phylo to work james lennox2Macintosh HD:blackwell/princeton:HPS Phylo to work james lennox-Macintosh HD:Desktop Folder:HPS Phylo to work88o(.@P_ [d\GCJOJQJmH FGCJOJQJmH GCJEHOJQJmH C$Eƀb'GCJEHOJQJmH FGCJEHOJQJmH  $dGCJOJQJmH $d6$d$dC$Eƀb'C$Eƀ6b'$d5ah;g>^'-5BHP1PQ 8X [ \    [ k l m n U V k y z {   0 1 4 8 Y    ( 7 f p  su PSpwz.13 0bju  "!L!Q!z!{!%%m(z((( )-)))1,>,S,T,Y,^,e,q,r,{,,,,,,. ..".3.4.?.@.Y.e......../////////002@2I2J222222338888<?<J<O<g?i?t?/@O@HHMMMOOT0TyWWWW&YSYVYYYYY)Z-Z8Z@ZfZgZZZZZZZZ[[:[Z[d[e[[[[[[[[[[[[[[\\\ \ \ \ \\\\\\\$\%\*\3\4\7\8\;\<\D\K\L\M\`\a\]]C^M^Q^^_D_O____jcd/deee-f/f0f1f2f3fgfhfifffffffgggg,g-g@gVg_gyggggiipiptpppppqqxx;y?yPyp{q{p$<P &')?@CDxyȊAb2/z~ōƍǍHijqtw̏͏MÐƐː̐L`pqϑБ^_d*45L_“Ó !ALMNO~Ԕ -<=HReʖ˖+=>QRЗїڗۗ<=LMؘ٘mșəNkls̛͛=G]}ץ٥:Ee ?@BFastħ˧̧')7ب٨ڨۨܨAͭޭDE]^}~ݮ13 0@1 1 @1 1 @1 1.@1 1"!12@1@1z!1!1!1!1@1@1!1@1"0n@1t@1\"1|@1"1@1"1"0@1"1"1<@1"1#1@1#1$@1j#1p#1r#1#1#0d@1$1@1$1"@1$12@1 $1@1@$1@1@1B$1f$1h$1x$1z$1P%1R%1|%1%1%1%1%1%1 &0 &1@1@1@1&1(&12&14&1Z&1\&1&1@1&1&1&1&1&1Z@1'1@1 '10'12'1n@18'1@1L'1d'1x'1'1'1'1 (14(1@1R(1@1t(1!@1(0$@1(1)1)1.@18)1b1@1:)1z1@1<)11@1B)1t2@1V)03@1f)1t)18@1z)1\8@1)18@1)18@1)18@1*1f*1l*18@1:@1p*1(;@1*0;@1*1;@1*0<@1*1>+0+1A@1+1,,16,1,0D@120L@1,1Q@1,06R@1,1TS@1,0xT@1-1FY@1-1Y@1 -1Y@1*-1B-1D-1V-1Y@1j-1Y@1p-1Z@1-1\@1-1\@1-1]@1-1]@1-1p]@1]@1-0]@1d.1^@1f.1,^@1h.1.1.1.1.1.1.1.1B/1H/0r_@1l/1/1c@1/1d@1J010101d@100f@101 q@100$q@101w@110w@1}@1&10~@1F0@1F0@121@0š@120ޞ@121d@121F@1L30\@131X@1314141@1@141B@141X@1514@15151651H51J51N5151"61$61h61616161F1<71717171t@17171@1717171717171717171818181818181 81"81081281<81N81P81V81X81^81`81p81~818181@1ҳ@10G1@181@181*91*:1:1:0@1;0ʺ@1R@1,;1@1b;1.@1;02G06G08G0:G0V@0X@1G0@1@G0f@1BG1JG1PG1@0<1@1RG0>@0TG1n@1VG1@1G1 @1@00@ 02@1G0@1@ 1@ 1G1*H16@ 1,H1@ 0@0@1.H0R@10H18H1@1ZH0@0@1V@1\H1dH1pH1H1 @1@1x0L1L1L1L1L1 M1 M1M1M1>x1|M1@x1M1Bx1M1Dx1M1N1DN1fN1jN1O1HO1O1P1Q1R1T1R1zS1&T1bT1dT1T1T1T1T1T1U1U1U1U1 V1V1V1,V1.V1.W1.X1bX1pX1rX0X1X1Y1Z1Fx1Z1Z1Z1*[1[1[1 \1\0Lx1\1\1\1\1\1\1]1]1]1^1~_1_   6bbb)S T | | 2pj L!L!!!!!!!!! ! ! ! ! !!!!!!!!!!!!!    4 #'L.G4:?E`KAPU\a3fj_nsVxe~%͏H͛dMA<    mzB  o=InQ3;<}bc 12u |!}!#%'(++.0G46z9<<<<>?AnDG\I)LMEOPPRRS Y_jc/f0f1f2f3fFfffg,g-gggjjjkkkLlMlNmOmnooppq)stdvevvVx{7߂- ͏M͛7c*TץܨU}23qҰӰ !!!!!!!!Y;\!iY!!iY!!wH!&'!b!!ӤU!@A!!ӤU! !!&'! - ! !!34!~&!.!!G8!!J;!!ӤU!< .!34!@A!!!!&'!!,!34!|D@!>" !<9!G!,!>" !@m!!@m!Ӳ!f!z!M!<9!@m!@m!@m!@m!@m!@m!@m!6!6!@m!6!@m!<9!@m} u    5!:"#$%&'()*+,-./012346789I;<=>?@AMCDEFGHJKLbNOPQRSTUVW^YZ[\]_`acdefghnopqrstvX{|~ody Text Indent 2 $\4B`b4 Body Text $dEH8P`r8 Body Text 2$d(DS"#%FJJK'LN]hchyiKmov݂P 6b)S T | 2p     6bbb))S | | | 2p PL!L!                   !      k4 #'L.G4:O@FKAP,V\.bfkn-tVx~ PMA<   t  \<(MyIxPl;<}bc 12u |!}!#%'(++.0G46z9<<<<>?AnDG\I)LMEOPPRRS Y_jc/f0f1f2f3fFfffg,g-gggjjjkkkLlMlNmOmnooppq)stdvevvVx{7߂- ̏-ͮ?1?1?1?1@1@1l@1n@1r@1@1@1@1@1@1A1A1A1A1A1A1A1 B1"B1$B0&B04#@1(B0(@1,@1I1,@1I1$J1,@1FJ1`B1TJ1jB1VJ1B1,C1.C1^C1`C1C1C1C1C1C1C1^D1zD1D0,@0V-@02@02@12@1x13@03@03@03@0 3@!!@m!G!@m!!@m!>" ! !@m! !@m!>" !!>" !,!@m! !>" !|D@!F!F!@m!>" !>" !@m!@m!@m!M!9Am!~&!i3!|D@!G!!@m!,!|D@!@m!!!!!!!!!GTimes New Roman5Symbol3 Arial3Times9Palatino"qh2X&X ?C>4d:History and Philosophy of Science: A Phylogenetic Approach Center for Philosophy of Science james lennox [(@(NormalCJmH @@@ Heading 1$$@& 5OJQJ<A@<Default Paragraph Font8>@8Title$d 5OJQJ8&@8Footnote ReferenceH*:@: Footnote Text CJOJQJJC@"JBody Text Indent$dOJQJ&)@1& Page NumbeL!L!                   !      k4 #'L.G4:O@FKAP,V\.bfkn-tVx~͏՛MA<   t  \<(MyIxPa;<}bc 12u |!}!#%'(++.0G46z9<<<<>?AnDG\I)LMEOPPRRS Y_jc/f0f1f2f3fFfffg,g-gggjjjkkkLlMlNmOmnooppq)stdvevvVx{7߂- ͏.Δ*]ǡ!!@m!@m!@m!!@m!@m!zY!iY!!iY!@m!F!~&!f`!@m!;S!|D@!@m!;S!>" !@m!~&! !>" !@m!i3!~&!,!G!G8!@m!<9!!;S!< .!i3!|D@!@m!@m!@m!~&!G!,!i3!|D@!>" !<9!G!,!>" !@m!!@m!Ӳ!f!z!M!<9!@m!@m!@m!@m!@m!@m!@m!6!6!@m!6!@m!<9!@m!!@m!G!@m!!@m!>" ! !@m! !@m!>" !!>" !,!@m! !>" !|D@!F!F!@m!>" !>" !@m!@m!@m!M!9Am!i3!i3!|D@!G!!@m!,!|D@!@m!!!!!;<}bc!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!6!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!;<}bc 12u |!}!#%'(++.0G46z9<<<<>?AnDG\I)LMEOPPRRS Y_jc/f0f1f2f3fFfffg,g-gggjjjkkkLlMlNmOmnooppq)stdvevvVx{7߂- ͏M͛7c*TץܨU}23qҰӰ  @ XN܀zhz "QlĊh^hzH|Unknown Center for Philosophy of Science james lennox !!  [ b *344=$= F !!!!##$#)#.#7###v$|$))k*t***++0015@55566%>->?@5I@I/K<B@S@DFHHKKNAOaWY YTYfZ[\\`bbbIfkfgg0gXghhMvOvx2ya{n{||1M} ͏̛6:06()=Däac5; 135oq Center for Philosophy of Science<Macintosh HD:Temporary Items:AutoRecovery save of HPS/Phylo Center for Philosophy of Science-Macintosh HD:Desktop Folder:HPS/Phylo to work Center for Philosophy of Science/Macintosh HD:Temporary Items:Word Work File A 1 Center for Philosophy of Science/Macintosh HD:Temporary Items:Word Work File A 1 Center for Philosophy of Science/Macintosh HD:Temporarynt accounts ofations, confirmation, and so on?ed as a rhetorical question, but in fact above dilemma Ron bite the naturalistic bullet: P at a stage on the way to the first response (I ve heard the history of the creation of my own department retold in these terms.) HPS first viewed as n Then the obvious  is/ought , epistemic naturalistic fallacy argument is chanted. And finally, people either reject the value of history of sicence for its philosophy, or  naturalize philosophy of science to solve the problem. of science--as a  source of phenomena against which to test theses in thehilosophy of science is one I completely reject. However, m role for thewithin theThe picture arose from reflecting on my own (unreflective) practice and the practice of those in the field from whom I had learned.trying to better bel is intended to highlight a (weak)ic, and (though a wider lens is needed) of science generally,,,ingthe use ofbriefly ection. It, unlike Darwin, Wallace was emphaticthe study of processes the possibility of (as it did for Charles Lyell, in fact). He Darwin to cast the metaphor ofbreedingFurthermore, clear How, precisely, the variety comes to replace the species (and note how confusing that idea itself is) is never discussed. I will later argue that it would likely also have had different philosophical problems.as to which, , This historical research opens and suggestivecontemporary theirs in biology s history. Go backto problems whichBut once is seen as itss a problem, have the resources to better understand it and its problematic status.  Let me stress that I am exploiting a metaphor I am not into evolutionary epistemology, and what follows is not an attempt at it.dless numbers of better designs for the skeletonof a creature that walks p Items:Word Work File A 1 Center for Philosophy of Science-Macintosh HD:Desktop Folder:HPS/Phylo to work james lennoxAMacintosh HD:Desktop Folder:blackwell/princeton:HPS Phylo to work james lennox2Macintosh HD:blackwell/princeton:HPS Phylo to work james lennox2Macintosh HD:blackwell/princeton:HPS Phylo to work james lennox2Macintosh HD:blackwell/princeton:HPS Phylo to work88o(.@B d\GCJOJQJmH FGCJOJQJmH GCJEHOJQJmH C$Eƀb'GCJEHOJQJmH FGCJEHOJQJmH  $dGCJOJQJmH $d6$d$dC$Eƀb'C$Eƀ6b'$d5ah;g>^'-5BHP1PQ 8X [ \    [ k l m n U V k y z {   0 1 4 8 Y    ( 7 f p  su PSpwz.13 0bju  "!L!Q!z!{!%%m(z((( )-)))1,>,S,T,Y,^,e,q,r,{,,,,,,. ..".3.4.?.@.Y.e......../////////002@2I2J222222338888<?<J<O<g?i?t?/@O@HHMMMOOT0TyWWWW&YSYVYYYYY)Z-Z8Z@ZfZgZZZZZZZZ[[:[Z[d[e[[[[[[[[[[[[[[\\\ \ \ \ \\\\\\\$\%\*\3\4\7\8\;\<\D\K\L\M\`\a\]]C^M^Q^^_D_O____jcd/deee-f/f0f1f2f3fgfhfifffffffgggg,g-g@gVg_gyggggiipiptpppppqqxx;y?yPyp{q{p$<P &')?@CDxyȊAb2/z~ōƍǍHijqtw̏͏MÐƐː̐L`pqϑБ^_d*45L_“Ó !ALMNO~Ԕ -<=HReʖ˖+=>QRЗїڗۗ<=LMؘ٘mșəNkls̛͛=G]}ץ٥:Ee ?@BFastħ˧̧')7ب٨ڨۨܨAͭޭDE]^}~ݮ13 0@1 1 @1 1 @1 1.@1 1"!12@1z!1!1!1!1@1@1!1@1"0n@1\"1|@1"1@1"1"0@1"1"1<@1"1#1@1#1$@1j#1p#1r#1#1#0d@1$1@1$1"@1$12@1 $1@1@$1@1@1B$1f$1h$1x$1z$1P%1R%1|%1%1%1%1%1%1 &0 &1@1@1@1&1(&12&14&1Z&1\&1&1@1&1&1&1&1&1Z@1'1@1 '10'12'1n@18'1@1L'1d'1x'1'1'1'1 (14(1@1R(1@1t(1!@1(0$@1(1)1)1.@18)1b1@1:)1z1@1<)11@1B)1t2@1V)03@1f)1t)18@1z)1\8@1)18@1)18@1)18@1*1f*1l*18@1:@1p*1(;@1*0;@1*1;@1*0<@1*1>+0+1A@1+1,,16,1,0D@120L@1,1Q@1,06R@1,1TS@1,0xT@1-1FY@1-1Y@1 -1Y@1*-1B-1D-1V-1Y@1j-1Y@1p-1Z@1-1\@1-1\@1-1]@1-1]@1-1p]@1]@1-0]@1d.1^@1f.1,^@1h.1.1.1.1.1.1.1.1B/1H/0r_@1l/1/1c@1/1d@1J010101d@100f@101 q@100$q@101w@110w@1}@1&10~@1F0@1F0@121@0š@120ޞ@121d@121F@1L30\@131X@1314141@1@141B@141X@1514@15151651H51J51N5151"61$61h61616161F1<71717171t@17171@1717171717171717171818181818181 81"81081281<81N81P81V81X81^81`81p81~818181@1ҳ@10G1@181@181*91*:1:1:0@1;0ʺ@1R@1,;1@1b;1.@1;02G06G08G0:G0V@0X@1G0@1@G0f@1BG1JG1PG1@0<1@1RG0>@0TG1n@1VG1@1G1 @1@00@ 02@1G0@1@ 1@ 1G1*H16@ 1,H1@ 0@0@1.H0R@10H18H1@1ZH0@0@1V@1\H1dH1pH1H1 @1@1x0L1L1L1L1L1 M1 M1M1M1>x1|M1@x1M1Bx1M1Dx1M1N1DN1fN1jN1O1HO1O1P1Q1R1T1R1zS1&T1bT1dT1T1T1T1T1T1U1U1U1U1 V1V1V1,V1.V1.W1.X1bX1pX1rX0X1X1Y1Z1Fx1Z1Z1Z1*[1[1[1 \1\0Lx1\1\1\1\1\1\1]1]1]1^1~_1_1_1_1_1`1`1`1`1`1Nx1x1pa1a0x1a1a1a1(b1b1b1b1b1b1>c1Zc1bc1bd1hd1jd1|d1~d1*e1,e14e1fe1e1e1e1e1e1e1f1f1f1f1f1g1,g1.g1g1g1g1g0g1^h1xh1zh1h1h1h1h1h1n1n1n1n1n1n1n0n1o1p1p18p18q1vq1zq1|q0h0h1r1\r1^r1r1r1r1r1hs1s1s1s1s1s1s1s1t10t1t1u0x1$@1H1@1@0@0 3@0@1FI0@1ZI1 @1I0!@1<1"<1<1I1:=1r=1t=1=1=1B>1D>1h>1>1>1>1>1>12?1V?1X?1?1?1?1?1?1?1?1@ 12u |!}!#%'(++.0G46z9<<<<>?AnDG\I)LMEOPPRRS Y_jc/f0f1f2f3fFfffg,g-gggjjjkkkLlMlNmOmnooppq)stdvevvVx{7߂- ͏.Δ*]ǡ.yglq=67 ¯ïbc?@ 0/ =!"#$%|HH(FG(HH(d'`arguingin this debate wasConverselyhow can the history of science have this descriptive character, given that order to delimit their subject? Moreover, don tto support differe !OJQJDR`RDBody Text Indent 2 $\4B`b4 Body Text $dEH(DS"#%FJJK'LN]hchyiKmov݂ 6b)S T | 2p     6bbb))S | | | 2p L!L!                   !      k4 #'L.G4:O@FKAP,V\.bfkn-tVx~͏ƛMA<   t  \<(MyIxPa;<}bc 12u |!}!#%'(++.0G46z9<<<<>?AnDG\I)LMEOPPRRS Y_jc/f0f1f2f3fFfffg,g-gggjjjkkkLlMlNmOmnooppq)stdvevvVx{7߂- ͏.ΔNjդX]bp֪.'( ST01!!@m!@m!@m!!@m!@m!zY!iY!!iY!@m!F!~&!f`!@m!;S!|D@!@m!;S!>" !@m!~&! !>" !@m!i3!~&!,!G!G8!@m!<9!!;S!< .!i3!|D@!@m!@m!@m!~&!G!,!i3!|D@!>" !<9!G!,!>" !@m!!@m!Ӳ!f!z!M!<9!@m!@m!@m!@m!@m!@m!@m!6!6!@m!6!@m!<9!@m!!@m!G!@m!!@m!>" ! !@m! !@m!>" !!>" !,!@m! !>" !|D@!F!F!@m!>" !>" !@m!@m!@m!M!9Am!i3!i3!|D@!G!!@m!,!|D@!@m!!!!!!!!!!!!! [(@(NormalCJmH @@@ Heading 1$$@& 5OJQJ<A@<Default Paragraph Font8>@8Title$d 5OJQJ8&@8Footnote ReferenceH*:@: Footnote Text CJOJQJJC@"JBody Text Indent$dOJQJ&)@1& Page Number4@B4Header  !OJQJDR`RDBody Text Indent 2 $\4B`b4 Body Text $dEH(DS"#%FJJK'LN]hchyiKmov݂ 6b)S T | 2p  d 1908 a number of people, including Yule, Castle, Pearson and Punnett worked on this problem. But it was a German dwho general T a friend and cricket mate of Hardy s, had presented a paper to the Royal Society of Medicine which provoked G. Yule to suggest, quoting Hardy,  as a criticism of the Mendelian position, that if brachydactyly is dominant  in the course of time one would expect, in the absence of coutneracting factors, to get three brachydactylous person to one normal .But, goes on,  [I]t is not hard to prove& that such an expectation would be quite groundless. Hardy proves that (alleles)And the result of this transformation is to prove that the conditions for a stable equilibrium of gene frequencies is established in one generation of random mating and that, in the absence of countervailing forces, the frequency distributions of alleles would remain unchanged in successive generations.provided had been developing a veryoperated from very different The following is a partial list of those different assumptions  In fact the above sketch of the story is mythical in a number of more straightforward ways. There is clear evidence that both Correns and De Vries were aware of Mendel s work years before their 1900 publications (cf. I. H. Stamhuis, O. G. Meijer, E. J. A. Zevenhuizen,  Hugo de Vries on heredity, 1889-1903: Statistics, Mendelian laws, pangenes, mutations , Isis, vol. 90 (1999) 238-267; H.-J. Rheinberger,  When did Carl Correns read Mendel s paper? , Isis, vol. 86 (1995) 612-618; R. C. Olb   6bbb)S T | | 2pj L!L!!!!!!!!! ! ! ! ! !!!!!!!!!!!!!    4 #'L.G4:?E`KAPU\a3fj_nsVxe~%͏H͛dMA<    !!!!!!!!!!!!!6!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!;<}bc 12u |!}!#%'(++.0G46z9<<<<>?AnDG\I)LMEOPPRRS Y_jc/f0f1f2f3fFfff o=InQ3;<}bc 12u |!}!#%'(++.0G46z9<<<<>?AnDG\I)LMEOPPRRS Y_jc/f0f1f2f3fFfffg,g-gggjjjkkkLlMlNmOmnooppq)stdvevvVx{7߂- ͏M͛7c*TץܨU}23qҰӰ !!!!!!!!Y;\!iY!!iY!!wH!&'!b!!ӤU!@A!!ӤU! !!&'! - ! !!34!~&!.!!G8!!J;!!ӤU!< .!34!@A!!!!&'!!,!34!|D@!>" !<9!G!,!>" !@m!!@m!Ӳ!f!z!M!<9!@m!@m!@m!@m!@m!@m!@m!6!6!@m!6!@m!<9!@mܚBCLQ!!@m!@m!@m!!@m!@m!zY!iY!!iY!@m!F!~&!f`!@m!;S!|D@!@m!;S!>" !@m!~&! !>" !@m!i3!~&!,!G!G8!@m!<9!!;S!< .!i3!|D@!@mg,g-gggjjjkkkLlMlNmOmnooppq)stdvevvVx{7߂- ͏.ΔNjդX]bp֪.'( ST01qr}~e sketched it is that there was a price to be paid for reconstructing the foundations of evolutionary theory in the mathematical language developed in order to describe the changes in the genetics of populations from one generation to the next. The price  @ XN܀zh  "QlĊh^h H|Unknown Center for Philosophy of Science james lennox !!  [ b *344=$= F !!!!##$#)#.#7###v$|$))k*t***++0015@55566%>->?@5I@I/K<B@S@DFHHKKNAOaWY YTYfZ[\\`bbbIfkfgg0gXghhMvOvx2ya{n{||1M} ͏M6<ŤBD26!#3pr Center for Philosophy of Science/Macintosh HD:Temporary Items:Word Work File A 1 Center for Philosophy of Science/Macintosh HD:Temporary Iteerched precariously on two hind-limbstinkering with a skeletal plan that is more history than adaptationmay   hat, whatever role they played, from a genuine 12  0/ =!"#$%|HH(FG(HH(d'`systematic rarelynot directly testabledevelopment of a number of laboratory techniquesto aid in the investigation ofw to apply this theory to natural populationsBetween 1902 an!!@m!G!@m!!@m!>" ! !@m! !@m!>" !!>" !,!@m! !>" !|D@!F!F!@m!>" !>" !@m!@m!@m!M!9Am!~&!i3!|D@!G!!@m!,!|D@!@m!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!6!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!;<}bc 12u |!}!#%'(++.0G46z9<<<<>?AnDG\I)LMEOPPRRS Y_jc/f0f1f2f3fFfffg,g-gggjjjkkkLlMlNmOmnooppq)stdvevvVx{7߂- ͏M͛7c*TץܨU}23qҰӰ  @ XN܀zhx "QlĊh^hxH|Unknown Center for Philosophy of Science james lennox !!  [ b *344=$= F !!!!##$#)#.#7###v$|$))k*t***++0015@55566%>->?@5I@I/K?@AMCDEFGHJKLbNOPQRSTUVW^YZ[\]_`acdefghijklwnopqrstvXx{| @ XN܀zh$ "QlĊh^h$H|Unknown Center for Philosophy of Science james lennox !!  [ b *344=$= F !!!!##$#)#.#7###v$|$))k*t***++0015@55566%>->?@5I@I/K<B@S@DFHHKKNAOaWY YTYfZ[\\`bbbIfkfgg0gXghhMvOvx2ya{n{||1M} ͏%z}\ƟʟơEKͤԤQSAEũ˩ì()02ůB Center for Philosophy of Science/Macintosh HD:Temporary Items:Word Work File A 1 Center for Philosophy of Science/Macintosh HD:Temporary Items:Word Work File A 1 Center for Philosophy of Science-Macintosh HD:Desktop Folder:HPS/Phylo to work james lennoxAMacintosh HD:Desktop Folder:blackwell/princeton:HPS Phylo to work james lennox2Macintosh HD:blackwell/princeton:HPS Phylo to work james lennox2Macintosh HD:blackwell/princeton:HPS Phylo to work james lennox2Macintosh HD:blackwell/princeton:HPS Phylo to work james lennox-Macintosh HD:Desktop Folder:HPS Phylo to work james lennox-Macintosh HD:Desktop Folder:HPS Phylo to work james lennox-Macintosh HD:Desktop Folder:HPS Phylo to work88o(.@ [565 5 d5\GCJOJQJmH 5FGCJOJQJmH 5GCJEHOJQJmH 5C$Eƀb'GCJEHOJQJmH 5FGCJEHOJQJmH 5$d5GCJOJQJmH 5$d56$d5$d5C$Eƀ5b'C$Eƀ56b'Tah;g>^'-5BHP1PQ 8X [ \    [ k l m n U V k y z {   0 1 4 8 Y    ( 7 f p  su PSpwz.13 0bju  "!L!Q!z!{!%%m(z((( )-)))1,>,S,T,Y,^,e,q,r,{,,,,,,. ..".3.4.?.@.Y.e......../////////002@2I2J222222338888<?<J<O<g?i?t?/@O@HHMMMOOT0TyWWWW&YSYVYYYYY)Z-Z8Z@ZfZgZZZZZZZZ[[:[Z[d[e[[[[[[[[[[[[[[\\\ \ \ \ \\\\\\\$\%\*\3\4\7\8\;\<\D\K\L\M\`\a\]]C^M^Q^^_D_O____jcd/deee-f/f0f1f2f3fgfhfifffffffgggg,g-g@gVg_gyggggiipiptpppppqqxx;y?yPyp{q{p$<P &')?@CDxyȊAb2/z~ōƍǍHijqtw̏͏MÐƐː̐L`c-.23PQhߒe͓56ACD”͔ΔϔД34=>U )*ɖӖ;KLfgmҗӗ'(,14?QR[\a͘ΘYZn ()*XYޚ 4B\]<Oͣף giʦզ'DyzϧЧҧ֧%&./15T[\Ǩ"#1:GMhijkl/ѭ39?]nzԮծ "m{ï0@1 1 @1 1 @1 1.@1 1"!12@1@1z!1!1!1!1@1@1!1@1"0n@1t@1\"1|@1"1@1"1"0@1"1"1<@1"1#1@1#1$@1j#1p#1r#1#1#0d@1$1@1$1"@1$12@1 $1@1@$1@1@1B$1f$1h$1x$1z$1P%1R%1|%1%1%1%1%1%1 &0 &1@1@1@1&1(&12&14&1Z&1\&1&1@1&1&1&1&1&1Z@1'1@1 '10'12'1n@18'1@1L'1d'1x'1'1'1'1 (14(1@1R(1@1t(1!@1(0$@1(1)1)1.@18)1b1@1:)1z1@1<)11@1B)1t2@1V)03@1f)1t)18@1z)1\8@1)18@1)18@1)18@1*1f*ms:Word Work File A 1 Center for Philosophy of Science/Macintosh HD:Temporary Items:Word Work File A 1 Center for Philosophy of Science-Macintosh HD:Desktop Folder:HPS/Phylo to work james lennoxAMacintosh HD:Desktop Folder:blackwell/princeton:HPS Phylo to work james lennox2Macintosh HD:blackwell/princeton:HPS Phylo to work james lennox2Macintosh HD:blackwell/princeton:HPS Phylo to work james lennox2Macintosh HD:blackwell/princeton:HPS Phylo to work james lennox-Macintosh HD:Desktop Folder:HPS Phylo to work james lennox-Macintosh HD:Desktop Folder:HPS Phylo to work88o(.@@\c [565 5 d5\GCJOJQJmH 5FGCJOJQJmH 5GCJEHOJQJmH 5C$Eƀb'GCJEHOJQJmH 5FGCJEHOJQJmH 5$d5GCJOJQJmH 5$d56$d5$d5C$Eƀ5b'C$Eƀ56b'0ah;g>^'-5BHP1PQ 8X [ \    [ k l m n U V k y z {   0 1 4 8 Y  019=Bߤ$/156ABJKNOTU\X_gl{¦ʦЦܦ%,4fqŧɧ9=w~ҨڨJPZc&,NW=FHQӯگܯ!;By~۰W2T'''()-),,22|56787<><B@S@DFHHKKNAOaWY YTYfZ[\\`bbbIfkfgg0gXghhMvOvx2ya{n{||1M} ͏M~̛6:06()=Däac5; 135oq Center for Philosophy of Science<Macintosh HD:Temporary Items:AutoRecovery save of HPS/Phylo Center for Philosophy of Science<Macintosh HD:Temporary Items:AutoRecovery save of HPS/Phylo Center for Philosophy of Science-Macintosh HD:Desktop Folder:HPS/Phylo to work Center for Philosophy of Science/Macintosh HD:Temporary Items:Word Work File A 1 Center for Philosophy of Science/Macintosh HD:Temporary Items:Word Work File A 1 Center for Philosophy of Science/Macintosh HD:Temporary Items:Word Work File A 1 Center for Philosophy of Science-Macintosh HD:Desktop Folder:HPS/Phylo to work james lennoxAMacintosh HD:Desktop Folder:blackwell/princeton:HPS Phylo to work james lennox2Macintosh HD:blackwell/princeton:HPS Phylo to work james lennox2Macintosh HD:blackwell/princeton:HPS Phylo to work88o(.@MMBML d\GCJOJQJmH FGCJOJQJmH GCJEHOJQJmH C$Eƀb'GCJEHOJQJmH FGCJEHOJQJmH  $dGCJOJQJmH  $d $d6$dC$Eƀy,  Horticulture: the font for the baptism of genetics , Nature Reviews: Genetics, Vol. 1 (October 2000) 65-70. Olby also clearly establishes that these thinkers, as well as Bateson, interpreted Mendel s results from distinct perspectives, each very different from Mendel s. Vol. 25 (1994) No. 1, As a note at the end of the paper makes clear, his paper is a response to the published version of Punnett s lecture, in which Yule s objection is reported. A succinct account of the work of Yule, Castle and Peason leading up to this result can be found in W. B. Provine, The Origins of Theoretical Population Genetics, Chicago, 1971 132-136.19  0/ =!"#$%|HH(FG(HH(d'`ss and  selection coefficient elephant expect, in the absence of count : due ences between populations After noting  some remarkable ald Fisher said,  fitness, sthe same mean fitnessithe conceptual and methodological assumptions that areresources availableAdd about 2 pages of results. Send to Alan.rs, along translations of the papers of drevidence that both Correns and dJ. A. , Classic Papers in Genetics, Englewood Cliffs, As hesin a postscript27  0/ =!"#$%|HH(FG(HH(d'` The example I just sketched a cartoon sketch at that was quite precisely one having to do with two concepts, fitness and natural selection. The lesson of the history as I hav   ( 7 f p  su PSpwz.13 0bju  "!L!Q!z!{!%%m(z((( )-)))1,>,S,T,Y,^,e,q,r,{,,,,,,. ..".3.4.?.@.Y.e......../////////002@2I2J222222338888<?<J<O<g?i?t?/@O@HHMMMOOT0TyWWWW&YSYVYYYYY)Z-Z8Z@ZfZgZZZZZZZZ[[:[Z[d[e[[[[[[[[[[[[[[\\\ \ \ \ \\\\\\\$\%\*\3\4\7\8\;\<\D\K\L\M\`\a\]]C^M^Q^^_D_O____jcd/deee-f/f0f1f2f3fgfhfifffffffgggg,g-g@gVg_gyggggiipiptpppppqqxx;y?yPyp{q{p$<P &')?@CDxyȊAb2/z~ōƍǍHijqtw̏͏MÐƐː̐L`c-.23PQhߒe͓56ACD”͔ΔϔД34=>U )*ɖӖ;KLfgmҗӗ'(,14?QR[\a͘ΘYZn IJyzϚ %3tMN-@ȣޤXZƦ5jk}çǧ "&ELMb'C$Eƀ6b' $d5ah;g>^'-5BHP1PQ 8X [ \    [ k l m n U V k y z {   0 1 4 8 Y    ( 7 f p  su PSpwz.13 0bju  "!L!Q!z!{!%%m(z((( )-)))1,>,S,T,Y,^,e,q,r,{,,,,,,. ..".3.4.?.@.Y.e......../////////002@2I2J222222338888<?<J<O<g?i?t?/@O@HHMMMOOT0TyWWWW&YSYVYYYYY)Z-Z8Z@ZfZgZZZZZZZZ[[:[Z[d[e[[[[[[[[[[[[[[\\\ \ \ \ \\\\\\\$\%\*\3\4\7\8\;\<\D\K\L\M\`\a\]]C^M^Q^^_D_O____jcd/deee-f/f0f1f2f3fgfhfifffffffgggg,g-g@gVg_gyggggiipiptpppppqqxx;y?yPyp{q{p$<P &')?@CDxyȊAb2/z~ōƍǍHijqtw̏͏MÐƐː̐L`pqϑБ^_d*45L_“Ó !ALMNO~Ԕ -<=HReʖ˖+=>QRЗїڗۗ<=LMؘ٘mșəNkls̛͛=G]}ץ٥:Ee ?@BFastħ˧̧')7ب٨ڨۨܨAͭޭDE]^}~ݮ13 0@1 1 @1 1 @1 1.@1 1"!12@1z!1!1!1!1@1@1!1@1"0n@1\"1|@1"1@1"1"0@1"1"1<@1"1#1@1#1$@1j#1p#1r#1#1#0d@1$1@1$1"@1$12@1 $1@1@$1@1@1B$1f$1h$1x$1z$1P%1R%1|%1%1%1%1%1%1 &0 &1@1@1@1&1(&12&14&1Z&1\&1&1@1&1&1&1&1&1Z@1'1@1 '10'12'1n@18'1@1L'1d'1x'1'1'1'1 (14(1@1R(1@1t(1!@1(0$@1(1)1)1.@18)1b1@1:)1z1@1<)11@1B)1t2@1V)03@1f)1t)18@1z)1\8@1)18@1)18@1)18@1*1f*1l*18@1:@1p*1(;@1*0;@1*1;@1*0<@1*1>+0+1A@1+1,,16,1,0D@120L@1,1Q@1,06R@1,1TS@1,0xT@1-1FY@1-1Y@1 -1Y@1*-1B-1D-1V-1Y@1j-1Y@1p-1Z@1-1\@1-1\@1-1]@1-1]@1-1p]@1]@1-0]@1d.1^@1f.1,^@1h.1.1.1.1.1.1.1.1B/1H/0r_@1l/1/1c@1/1d@1J010101d@100f@101 q@100$q@101w@110w@1}@1&10~@1F0@1F0@121@0š@120ޞ@121d@121F@1L30\@131X@1314141@1@141B@141X@1514@15151651H51J51N5151"61$61h61616161F1<71717171t@17171@1717171717171717171818181818181 81"81081281<81N81P81V81X81^81`81p81~818181@1ҳ@10G1@181@181*91*:1:1:0@1;0ʺ@1R@1,;1@1b;1.@1;02G06G08G0:G0V@0X@1G0@1@G0f@1astically endorsed connotations of struggle and  survival of the fittest that popularizations of Darwinism tended (and still tend) to stress. Even if that is true as an account of their motivations, however, it was the redefinition of the concepts of  fitness and  selection as mathematical variables that accomplished the task. I have argued that Fisher and Wright were both, in their own ways, aware of the downside of this move; but that modern accounts of the theory of natural selection have, to their peril, forgotten this history. To their peril, because it is a history built into this concept. Another example of the use of the history of the foundations of a discipline to better understand tensions and conflicts in them has been recently pointed out to me by my colleague Paul Griffiths. In a forthcoming review he characterizes James Griessemer s contribution to Beurton, Falk, Rheinberger eds., The Concept of the Gene in Development and Evolution: Historical and Epistemological Perspectives. And Alan Love s contribution to this workshop is another case in point. Love s project is, however, more ambitious and daunting. The philosophical issue he is interested in is that of the preconditions for explanatory integration across disciplines case in point: what would it take to make evo-devo work? Now history becomes important here in the first instance because it gives us a number of clues as to why this is a problem in the first place. Since organisms have developmental life histories and populations BG1JG1PG1@0<1@1RG0>@0TG1n@1VG1@1G1 @1@00@ 02@1G0@1@ 1@ 1G1*H16@ 1,H1@ 0@0@1.H0R@10H18H1@1ZH0@0@1V@1\H1dH1pH1H1 @1@1x0L1L1L1L1L1 M1 M1M1M1>x1|M1@x1M1Bx1M1Dx1M1N1DN1fN1jN1O1HO1O1P1Q1R1T1R1zS1&T1bT1dT1T1T1T1T1T1U1U1U1U1 V1V1V1,V1.V1.W1.X1bX1pX1rX0X1X1Y1Z1Fx1Z1Z1Z1*[1[1[1 \1\0Lx1\1\1\1\1\1\1]1]1]1^1~_1_1_1_1_1`1`1`1`1`1Nx1x1pa1a0x1a1a1a1(b1b1b1b1b1b1>c1Zc1bc1bd1hd1jd1|d1~d1*e1,e14e1fe1e1e1e1e1e1e1f1f1f1f1f1g1,g1.g1g1g1g1g0g1^h1xh1zh1h1h1h1h1h1n1n1n1n1n1n1n0n1o1p1p18p18q1vq1zq1|q0h1r1\r1^r1r1r1r1r1hs1s1s1s1s1s1s1s1t10t1t1u0x1$@1H1@1@0@0 3@0@1FI0@1ZI1 @1I0!@1<1"<1<1I1:=1r=1t=1=1=1B>1D>1h>1>1>1>1>1>12?1V?1X?1?1?1?1 "+8>YZ[\] ­$*0N_krwxyŮƮޮ߮ ^lqr0@1 1 @1 1 @1 1.@1 1"!12@1@1z!1!1!1!1@1@1!1@1"0n@1t@1\"1|@1"1@1"1"0@1"1"1<@1"1#1@1#1$@1j#1p#1r#1#1#0d@1$1@1$1"@1$12@1 $1@1@$1@1@1B$1f$1h$1x$1z$1P%1R%1|%1%1%1%1%1%1 &0 &1@1@1@1&1(&12&14&1Z&1\&1&1@1&1&1&1&1&1Z@1'1@1 '10'12'1n@18'1@1L'1d'1x'1'1'1'1 (14(1@1R(1@1t(1!@1(0$@1(1)1)1.@18)1b1@1:)1z1@1<)11@1B)1t2@1V)03@1f)1t)18@1z)1\8@1)18@1)18@1)18@1*1f*1l*18@1:@1p*1(;@1*0;@1*1;@1*0<@1*1>+0+1A@1+1,,16,1,0D@120L@1,1Q@1,06R@1,1TS@1,0xT@1-1FY@1-1Y@1 -1Y@1*-1B-1D-1V-1Y@1j-1Y@1p-1Z@1-1\@1-1\@1-1]@1-1]@1-1p]@1]@1-0]@1d.1^@1f.1,^@1h.1.1.1.1.1.1.1.1B/1H/0r_@1l/1/1c@1/1d@1J010101d@100f@101 q@100$q@101w@110w@1}@1&10~@1F0@1F0@121@0š@120ޞ@121d@121F@1L30\@131X@1314141@1@141B@141X@1514@15151651H51J51N5151"61$61h61616161F1<71717171t@17171@1717171717171717171818181818181 81"81081281<81N81P81V81X81^81`81p81~818181@1ҳ@10G1@181@181*91*:1:1:0@1;0ʺ@1R@1,;1@1b;1.@1;02G06G08G0:G0V@0X@1G0@1@G0f@1BG1JG1PG1@0<1@1RG0>@0TG1n@ 1VG1@ 1G1 @ 1@ 00@ 02@1G0@1@ 1@ 1G1*H16@1,H1@ 0@0@1.H0R@10H18H1@1ZH0@0@1V@1\H1dH1pH1H1 @1@1x0L1L1L1L1L1 M1 M1M1M1>x1|M1@x1M1Bx1M1Dx1M1N1DN1fN1jN1O1HO1O1P1Q1R1T1R1zS1&T1bT1dT1T1T1T1T1T1U1U1U1U1 V1V1V1,V1.V1.W1.X1bX1pX1rX0X1X1Y1Z1Fx1Z1Z1Z1*[1[1~1~1[1 \1\0Lx1\1\1\1\1\1\1]1]1]1^1~_1_1_1_1_1`1`1`1`1`1Nx1x1pa1a0x1a1a1a1(b1b1b1b1b1b1>c1Zc1bc1bd1hd1jd1|d1~d1*e1,e14e1fe1e1e1e1e1e1e1f1f1f1f1f1g1,g1.g1g1g1g1g0g1^h1xh1zh1h1h1h1h1h1n1n1n1n1n1n1n0n1o1p1p18p18q1vq1zq1|q0h0h1r1\r1^r1r1r1r1r1hs1s1s1s1s1s1s1s1t10t1t1u0x1$@1H1@1@0@0 3@0@1FI0@1ZI1 @1I0!@1<1"<1<1I1:=1r=1t=1=1=1B>1D>1h>1>1>1>1>1>12?1V?1X?1?1?1?1?1?1?1?1@1@1l@1n@1r@1@1@1@1@1@1A1A1A1A1A1A1A1 B1"B1$B0&B04#@1(B0(@1,@1I1,@1I1$J1,@1FJ1`B1TJ1jB1VJ1B1,C1.C1^C1`C1C1C1C1C1C1C1^D1zD1D0,@0V-@02@02@12@113@03@03@03@0 3@GTimes New Roman5XNYN1P;PZZ4[9[_[h[\\%\,\1\2\7\8\j\z\\\\\\\\\]]]1]4]@]A]]]^^^^____9``'a(accccceeggbieiijjmmn(oaoboqqqrptqtvvwyy{{mn܀j0JEHU5>*EH 5CJEH>*56 j0JUWQQ^SXj\{\\]A])acccdGddeehhhhiijjl$d$d $dl(m)mmmbop2rssrtu/y|o#tuÊĊ$d $ & Fd $d $hd$d|o#tuÊ&akef<vwJK'(htuv ) *{/ׇ)܀'EuĊŊъjxʌ݌&'abVlwҏQY[pryőܑ<Qs#RklGefg <=<CwxTzH*6CJCJj0JCJU j0JU56YĊ&akef<vwJK'(h$$1$$1$$zΗ3JKLZw '()9Vijpqrstvw}~\""....B/H/<1@1B12< <>>??r@@(BTBzDDE E EHFItJxJzJLSSS``hhH*5CJ0JmH0J j0JU6CJ 6CJEHCJEHCJj0JCJU6 j0JUNhituv&+B1<(B E6G8G:G4d:History and Philosophy of Science: A Phylogenetic Approach Center for Philosophy of Science james lennoxDocumentSummaryInformation8CompObjXObjectPoolM@`M@`0Table1@1l@1n@1r@1@1@1@1@1@1A1A1A1A1A1A1A1 B1"B1$B0&B04#@1(B0(@1,@1I1,@1I1$J1,@1FJ1`B1TJ1jB1VJ1B1,C1.C1^C1`C1C1C1C1C1C1C1^D1zD1D0,@0V-@02@02@12@1z13@03@03@03@0 3@GTimes New Roman5Symbol3 Arial3Times9Palatino"qh2X&X AC>4d:History and Philosophy of Science: A Phylogenetic Approach Center for Philosophy of Science james lennox [(@!@m!@m!~&!G!,!i3!|D@!>" !<9!G!,!>" !@m!!@m!Ӳ!f!z!M!<9!@m!@m!@m!@m!@m!@m!@m!6!6!@m!6!@m!<9!@m!!@m!G!@m!!@m!>" ! !@m! !@m!>" !!>" !,!@m! !>" !|D@!F!F!@m!>" !>" !@m!@m!M!9Am!i3!i3!|D@!G!!G!,!|D@!@m!!!!!;<}bc 12u |!}!#%'(++.0G46z9<<<<>?AnDG\I)LMEOPPRRS Y_jc/f0f1f2f3fFfffg,g-gggjjjkkkLlMlNmOmnooppq)stdvevvVx{7߂- ̏-͔ܚBCyl+#1tuͰ_^23>?@LMNQ  XN܀zhr "QlĊh^hrH|Unknown Center for Philosophy of Science james lennox !!  [ b *344=$= F !!!!##$#)#.#7###v$|$))k*t***++0015@55566%>->?@5I@I/K<B@S@DFHHKKNAOaWY YTYfZ[\\`bbbIfkfgg0gXghhMvOvx2ya{n{||1M|̏ЛĞǞCx|rxŢТjkw}OPsuڮۮw°ðư13Q Center for Philosophy of Science/Macintosh HD:Temporary Items:Word Work File A 1 Center for Philosophy of Science-Macintosh HD:Desktop Folder:HPS/Phylo to work james lennoxAMacintosh HD:Desktop Folder:blackwell/princeton:HPS Phylo to work james lennox2Macintosh HD:blackwell/princeton:HPS Phylo to work james lennox2Macintosh HD:blackwell/princeton:HPS Phylo to work james lennox2Macintosh HD:blackwell/princeton:HPS Phylo to work james lennox-Macintosh HD:Desktop Folder:HPS Phylo to work james lennox-Macintosh HD:Desktop Folder:HPS Phylo to work james lennox-Macintosh HD:Desktop Folder:HPS Phylo to work Center for Philosophy of Science1Macintosh HD:Desktop Folder:HPS Phylo to work.doc88o(.@B\!5565 5 d5\GCJOJQJmH 5FGCJOJQJmH 5GCJEHOJQJmH 5C$Eƀb'GCJEHOJQJmH 5FGCJEHOJQJmH 5$d5GCJOJQJmH 5$d56$d5GCJOJQJmH F5GCJOJQJmH C$Eƀ5b'C$Eƀ56b'ah;g>^'-5BHP1PQ 8X [ \    [ k l m n U V k y z {   0 1 4 8 Y    ( 7 f p  su PSpwz.13 0bju  "!L!Q!z!{!%%m(z((( )-)))1,>,S,T,Y,^,e,q,r,{,,,,,,. ..".3.4.?.@.Y.e......../////////002@2I2J222222338888<?<J<O<g?i?t?/@O@HHMMMOOT0TyWWWW&YSYVYYYYY)Z-Z8Z@ZfZgZZZZZZZZ[[:[Z[d[e[[[[[[[[[[[[[[\\\ \ \ \ \\\\\\\$\%\*\3\4\7\8\;\<\D\K\L\M\`\a\]]C^M^Q^^_D_O____jcd/deee-f/f0f1f2f3fgfhfifffffffgggg,g-g@gVg_gyggggiipiptpppppqqxx;y?yPyp{q{p#;O %&(>?BCwxNJߊ@a1.y}čōƍGhipsvˏ̏LŐʐːK_b,-12OPgޒߒd̓ߓ45@BC͔̔Δϔ23<=T()ȖҖ:JKeflїҗ&'+03>PQZ[`̘͘XYm GRSpqɚʚ˚͚ښۚܚ :;ST›ΛЛқ5CGBCUV|çħ٧+,>bרب @ACZ[iky˩ԩթˬ ,389:Iǯȯ̯ԯ-[su23@HJKMNOP0@1 1 @1 1 @1 1.@1 1"!12@1@1z!1!1!1!1@1@1!1@1"0n@1t@1\"1|@1"1@1"1"0@1"1"1<@1"1#1@1#1$@1j#1p#1r#1#1#0d@1$1@1$1"@1$12@1 $1@1@$1@1@1B$1f$1h$1x$1z$1P%1R%1|%1%1%1%1%1%1 &0 &1@1@1@1&1(&12&14&1Z&1\&1&1@1&1&1&1&1&1Z@1'1@1 '10'12'1n@18'1@1L'1d'1x'1'1'1'1 (14(1@1R(1@1t(1!@1(0$@1(1)1)1.@18)1b1@1:)1z1@1<)11@1B)1t2@1V)03@1f)1t)18@1z)1\8@1)18@1)18@1)18@1*1f*1l*18@1:@1p*1(;@1*0;@1*1;@1*0<@1*1>+0+1A@1+1,,16,1,0D@120L@1,1Q@1,06R@1,1TS@1,0xT@1-1FY@1-1Y@1 -1Y@1*-1B-1D-1V-1Y@1j-1Y@1p-1Z@1-1\@1-1\@1-1]@1-1]@1-1p]@1]@1-0]@1d.1^@1f.1,^@1h.1.1.1.1.1.1.1.1B/1H/0r_@1l/1/1l*18@1:@1p*1(;@1*0;@1*1;@1*0<@1*1>+0+1A@1+1,,16,1,0D@120L@1,1Q@1,06R@1,1TS@1,0xT@1-1FY@1-1Y@1 -1Y@1*-1B-1D-1V-1Y@1j-1Y@1p-1Z@1-1\@1-1\@1-1]@1-1]@1-1p]@1]@1-0]@1d.1^@1f.1,^@1h.1.1.1.1.1.1.1.1B/1H/0r_@1l/1/1c@1/1d@1J010101d@100f@101 q@100$q@101w@110w@1}@1&10~@1F0@1F0@121@0š@120ޞ@121d@121F@1L30\@131X@1314141@1@141B@141X@1514@15151651H51J51N5151"61$61h61616161F1<71717171t@17171@1717171717171717171818181818181 81"81081281<81N81P81V81X81^81`81p81~818181@1ҳ@10G1@181@181*91*:1:1:0@1;0ʺ@1R@1,;1@1b;1.@1;02G06G08G0:G0V@0X@1G0@1@G0f@1BG1JG1PG1@0<1@1RG0>@0TG1n@ 1VG1@ 1G1 @ 1@ 00@ 02@1G0@1@ 1@ 1G1*H16@1,H1@ 0@0@1.H0R@10H18H1@1ZH0@0@1V@1\H1dH1pH1H1 @1@1x0L1L1L1L1L1 M1 M1M1M1>x1|M1@x1M1Bx1M1Dx1M1N1DN1fN1jN1O1HO1O1P1Q1R1T1R1zS1&T1bT1dT1T1T1T1T1T1U1U1U1U1 V1V1V1,V1.V1.W1.X1bX1pX1rX0X1X1Y1Z1Fx1Z1Z1Z1*[1[1~1~1[1 \1\0Lx1\1\1\1\1\1\1]1]1]1^1~_1_1_1_1_1`1`1`1`1`1Nx1x1pa1a0x1a1a1a1(b1b1b1b1b1b1>c1Zc1bc1bd1hd1jd1|d1~d1*e1,e14e1fe1e1e1e1e1e1e1f1f1f1f1f1g1,g1.g1g1g1g1g0g1^h1xh1zh1h1h1h1h1h1n1n1n1n1n1n1n0n1o1p1p18p18q1vq1zq1|q0h1110h1r1\r1^r1r1r1r1r1hs1s1s1s1s1s1s1s1t10t1t1u0x1$@1H1@1@0@0 3@0@1FI0@1ZI1 @1I0!@1<1"<1<1I1:=1r=1t=1=1=1B>1D>1h>1>1>1>1>1>12?1V?1X?1?1?1?1?1?1?1?1@1@1l@1n@1r@1@1@1@1@1@1A1A1A1A1A1A1A1 B1"B1$B0&B04#@1(B0(@1,@1I1,@1I1$J1,@1FJ1`B1TJ1jB1VJ1B1,C1.C1^C1`C1C1C1C1C1C1C1^D1zD1D0,@0V-@02@02@12@113@03@03@03@0 3@GTimes New Roman5Symbol3 Arial3Times9Palatino"qh2X&X& C>4d:History and Philosophy of Science: A Phylogenetic Approach Center for Philosophy of Science james lennox|܃3'ˆMA9Yg{>[5NGԣ!oe:]/R, [s DCE[t Qq޷ljmmء%=y08IQTԝU@i<@ͯm@7Yz} 1iCIR-j-,9]b? o!zs)X EMv=6MCu҂ ,d?a٥rYdq3*NMѩ%A25f5וɕE[!we᭹^B]|m2>~D[  1_1_1_1`1`1`1`1`1Nx1x1pa1a0x1a1a1a1(b1b1b1b1b1b1>c1Zc1bc1bd1hd1jd1|d1~d1*e1,e14e1fe1e1e1e1e1e1e1f1f1f1f1f1g1,g1.g1g1g1g1g0g1^h1xh1zh1h1h1h1h1h1n1n1n1n1n1n1n0n1o1p1p18p18q1vq1zq1|q0h0h1r1\r1^r1r1r1r1r1hs1s1s1s1s1s1s1s1t10t1t1u0x1$@1H1@1@0@0 3@0@1FI0@1ZI1 @1I0!@1<1"<1<1I1:=1r=1t=1=1=1B>1D>1h>1>1>1>1>1>12?1V?1X?1?1?1?1?1?1?1?1@1@1l@1n@1r@1@1@1@1@1@1A1A1A1A1A1A1A1 B1"B1$B0&B04#@1(B0(@1,@1I1,@1I1$J1,@1FJ1`B1TJ1jB1VJ1B1,C1.C1^C1`C1C1C1C1C1C1C1^D1zD1D0,@0V-@02@02@12@1|13@03@03@03@0 3@GTimes New Roman5Symbol3 Arial3Times9Palatino"qh2X&X& CC>4d:History and Philosophy of Science: A Phylogenetic Approach Center for Philosophy of Science james lennox [(@(NormalCJmH @@@ Heading 1$$@& 5OJQJ<A@<Default Paragraph Font8>@8Title$d 5OJQJ8&@8Footnote ReferenceH*:@: Footnote Text CJOJQJJC@"JBody Text Indent FMicrosoft Word DocumentNB6WWord.Document.8 ՜.+,D՜.+,< hp  'University of PittsburghosC: ;History and Philosophy of Science: A Phylogenetic Approach Title 6> _PID_GUID'AN{6EE5D001-8A4C-11D5-8833-0000C5469FF8} Oh+'0 ( @L h t ';History and Philosophy of Science: A Phylogenetic Approacheist!Center for Philosophy of Science: AentNormalf james lennoxilo13eMicrosoft Word 8.0h@A:@ @,7)o<Origin p. 434>29 c jbjbSS 11]Fz`:::$LLL8,<ҹ$zz(,":::rN::N0~0ڭ0 0::h>::= ҹz LHistory and Philosophy of Science: A Phylogenetic Approach James G. Lennox, Department of History and Philosophy of Science Center for Philosophy of Science University of Pittsburgh 1. Introduction About twenty-five years ago, in the aftermath of Thomas Kuhns The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, there was a flurry of articles and book chapters dealing with the vexed question of the relationship between the history of science and the philosophy of science. The wider issue at stake was normativism versus naturalism in epistemology. If the history of science, at best, gives us reliable information about what actually occurred during the development of the sciences, how is it to support the inevitably normative conclusions of the philosophy of science? On the other hand, historians must make prior judgments about what counts as science in order to delimit their subject, and philosophers have to use similar standards in deciding what counts as the historical data base for discussions of scientific laws, theories, explanations, confirmation, and so on. Kuhn closed the Introduction to The Structure of Scientific Revolutions with what was clearly intended as a rhetorical question, one which presents the problem in stark terms: How could history of science fail to be a source of phenomena to which theories about knowledge may legitimately be asked to apply? (Kuhn 1970, 9) One response to this problem--Gieres, in fact--was to bite the naturalistic bullet: philosophy of science (or better, science studies) is just one more empirical inquiry into a human activity, drawing its standards from a careful examination of the historical record or of present day science, including its standards for what counts as science. Whatever people at different times took to be science is considered to be science. The philosopher is not in a position to legislate such matters. Another response--also Gieres--was the cynics: the connection between the history and philosophy of science is a marriage of convenience. When historians threw the internalist historians of science out of the history departments, they needed a home. Tom Kuhn created one for them, in philosophy departments. You will notice that, despite their different responses to the problem, Giere and Kuhn see the problem, as do many others, in the same way. The history of science is a sort of inductive data base to be used as confirmation for various philosophical views about science. This is a picture of the relationship between history and philosophy of science I completely reject. My primary goal in this essay is not to argue against this picture, however, but to present an alternative view of the relationship between history of science and philosophy of science. After many years of doing the history and philosophy of biology in a certain way, I spent some time reflecting on what it was I was doing. It was decidedly not the enterprise of trying to support philosophical conclusions with historical facts. It was rather the activity of undeof organisms are slices of evolutionary histories, a visitor from the mid- to late 19th century might be utterly puzzled that evolutionary and developmental studies were conceived us a separate disciplines in the first place. But history may have much more work to do here. As Alan Love has begun to show us, the story of the  exclusion of embryology/developmental biology from the synthesis is only part of the answer to the question of why philosophical work needs to be done toward integrating evolutionary and developmental studies. An equally significant  exclusion relates to another puzzling feature of the current revival of interest in development the renewed interest in the biological investigation of form functional morphology. In some writers who created, and now defend, the neo-Darwinian synthesis, neo-Darwinism is virtually synonymous with the rejection of morphology which they associate with essentialism, typology, and sometimes with German idealism.  Population thinking is the key to the triumph of Darwinism, and it swept away morphology. Well, perhaps& but Charles Darwin didn t see it that way. 28 ^hhhhoqjvNxxxxz| $$d$dhhnnvqzqqqqdvhvjvxxxzz|| "$0JmHH*6 In the Origin, recall, he closes his discussion of difficulties for his theory with a paragraph on those  two great laws governing the formation of organism: Unity of Type and Conditions of Existence. By unity of type is meant that fundamental agreement in structure, which we see in organic beings of the same class, and which is quite independent of their habits of life. On my theory, unity of type is explained by unity of descent. [1st ed., 206]28 Add to that his strong endorsement of Asa Gray s claim that Darwin had replaced the dichotomy  morphology vs. teleology by presiding over their wedding, and it is clear that this is not the Darwin beloved of  population thinking Darwinians. In order to understand the marginalization of functional morphology, and the even more interesting reappearance of terms like Bauplan in recent numbers of respected journals, I would argue we will need to do some serious historical work, of the sort being recommended by Alan Love in his contribution to this workshop.29 e problems they are facing.     rie pmental studies were conceived as 30 27 2 as using the history of the tensions inherent in contemporary developmental biology to point the way to resolving those tensions.30 1c@1/1d@1J010101d@100f@101 q@100$q@101w@110w@1}@1&10~@1F0@1F0@121@0š@120ޞ@121d@121F@1L30\@131X@1314141@1@141B@141X@1514@15151651H51J51N5151"61$61h61616161F1<71717171t@17171@1717171717171717171818181818181 81"81081281<81N81P81V81X81^81`81p81~818181@1ҳ@10G1@181@181*91*:1:1:0@1;0ʺ@1R@1,;1@1b;1.@1;02G06G08G0:G0V@0X@1G0@1@G0f@1BG1JG1PG1@0<1@1RG0>@0TG1n@ 1VG1@ 1G1 @ 1@ 00@ 02@1G0@1@ 1@ 1G1*H16@1,H1@ 0@0@1.H0R@10H18H1@1ZH0@0@1V@1\H1dH1pH1H1 @1@1x0L1L1L1L1L1 M1 M1M1M1>x1|M1@x1M1Bx1M1Dx1M1N1DN1fN1jN1O1HO1O1P1Q1R1T1R1zS1&T1bT1dT1T1T1T1T1T1U1U1U1U1 V1V1V1,V1.V1.W1.X1bX1pX1rX0X1X1Y1Z1Fx1Z1Z1Z1*[1[1~1~1[1 \1\0Lx1\1\1\1\1\1\1]1]1]1^1~_1_1_1_1_1`1`1`1`1`1Nx1x1pa1a0x1a1a1a1(b1b1b1b1b1b1>c1Zc1bc1bd1hd1jd1|d1~d1*e1,e14e1fe1e1e1e1e1e1e1f1f1f1f1f1g1,g1.g1g1g1g1g0g1^h1xh1zh1h1h1h1h1h1n1n1n1n1n1n1n0n1o1p1p18p18q1vq1zq1|q011^1t1v111b1d1f11j0h1r1\r1^r1r1r1r1r1hs1s1s1s1s1s1s1s1t10t1t1u0x1$@1H1@1@!0@0 3@0@1FI0@1ZI1 @1I0!@1<1"<1<1I1:=1r=1t=1=1=1B>1D>1h>1>1>1>1>1>12?1V?1X?1?1?1?1?1?1?1?1@1@1l@1n@1r@1@1@1@1@1@1A1A1A1A1A1A1A1 B1"B1$B0&B04#@1(B0(@1,@1I1,@1I1$J1,@1FJ1`B1TJ1jB1VJ1B1,C1.C1^C1`C1C1C1C1C1C1C1^D1zD1D0,@0V-@02@02@12@1l13@03@03@03@0 3@GTimes New Roman5Symbol3 Arial3Times9Palatino"ph2X&ީXFC!>4dB:History and Philosophy of Science: A Phylogenetic Approach Center for Philosophy of Science Center for Philosophy of ScienceDocumentSummaryInformation8CompObjXObjectPoolM@`M@`0Table1T1T1T1T1T1U1U1U1U1 V1V1V1,V1.V1.W1.X1bX1pX1rX0X1X1Y1Z1Fx1Z1Z1Z1*[1[1~1~1[1 \1\0Lx1\1\1\1\1\1\1]1]1]1^1~_1_1_1_1_1`1`1`1`1`1Nx1x1pa1a0x1a1a1a1(b1b1b1b1b1b1>c1Zc1bc1bd1hd1jd1|d1~d1*e1,e14e1fe1e1e1e1e1e1e1f1f1f1f1f1g1,g1.g1g1g1g1g0g1^h1xh1zh1h1h1h1h1h1n1n1n1n1n1n1n0n1o1p1p18p18q1vq1zq1|q0h0h1r1\r1^r1r1r1r1r1hs1s1s1s1s1s1s1s1t10t1t1u0x1$@1H1@1@0@0 3@0@1FI0@1ZI1 @1I0!@1<1"<1<1I1:=1r=1t=1=1=1B>1D>1h>1>1>1>1>1>12?1V?1X?1?1?1?1?1?1?1?1@1@1l@1n@1r@1@1@1@1@1@1A1A1A1A1A1A1A1 B1"B1$B0&B04#@1(B0(@1,@1I1,@1I1$J1,@1FJ1`B1TJ1jB1VJ1B1,C1.C1^C1`C1C1C1C1C1C1C1^D1zD1D0,@0V-@02@02@12@113@03@03@03@0 3@GTimes New Roman5Symbol3 Arial3Times9Palatino"qh2X&X& MC>4d:History and Philosophy of Science: A Phylogenetic Approach Center for Philosophy of Science james lennox [(@(NormalCJmH @ FMicrosoft Word DocumentNB6WWord.Document.8 ՜.+,D՜.+,< hp  'University of PittsburghosC: ;History and Philosophy of Science: A Phylogenetic Approach Title 6> _PID_GUID'AN{6EE5D001-8A4C-11D5-8833-0000C5469FF8} Oh+'0 ( T` |  ';History and Philosophy of Science: A Phylogenetic Approacheist!Center for Philosophy of Science: AentNormalf!Center for Philosophy of Science: A14tMicrosoft Word 8.0h@µ;@ @lƜ4* Indeed, in the section of chapter 13 entitled  Morphology , he refers to morphology as  the most interesting department of natural history, and may be said to be its very soul. []30 c jbjbSS 11C]/`c8,?<w$ (111111 """""",N>#11111NA11rAAA1B11 030001 AlA {wd sHistory and Philosophy of Science: A Phylogenetic Approach James G. Lennox, Department of History and Philosophy of Science Center for Philosophy of Science University of Pittsburgh 1. Introduction About twenty-five years ago, in the aftermath of Thomas Kuhns The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, there was a flurry of articles and book chapters dealing with the vexed question of the relationship between the history of science and the philosophy of science. The wider issue at stake was normativism versus naturalism in epistemology. If the history of science, at best, gives us reliable information about what actually occurred during the development of the sciences, how is it to support the inevitably normative conclusions of the philosophy of science? On the other hand, historians must make prior judgments about what counts as science in order to delimit their subject, and philosophers have to use similar standards in deciding what counts as the historical data base for discussions of scientific laws, theories, explanations, confirmation, and so on. Kuhn closed the Introduction to The Structure of Scientific Revolutions with what was clearly intended as a rhetorical question, one which presents the problem in stark terms: How could history of science fail to be a source of phenomena to which theories about knowledge may legitimately be asked to apply? (Kuhn 1970, 9) One response to this problem--Gieres, in fact--was to bite the naturalistic bullet: philosophy of science (or better, science studies) is just one more empirical inquiry into a human activity, drawing its standards from a careful examination of the historical record or of present day science, including its standards for what counts as science. Whatever people at different times took to be science is considered to be science. The philosopher is not in a position to legislate such matters. Another response--also Gieres--was the cynics: the connection between the history and philosophy of science is a marriage of convenience. When historians threw the internalist historians of science out of the history departments, they needed a home. Tom Kuhn created one for them, in philosophy departments. You will notice that, despite their different responses to the problem, Giere and Kuhn see the problem, as do many others, in the same way. The history of science is a sort of inductive data base to be used as confirmation for various philosophical views about science. This is a picture of the relationship between history and philosophy of science I completely reject. My primary goal in this essay is not to argue against this picture, however, but to present an alternative view of the relationship between history of science and philosophy of science. After many years of doing the history and philosophy of biology in a certain way, I spent some time reflecting on what it was I was doing. It was decidedly not the enterprise of trying to support philosophical conclusions with historical facts. It was rather the activity of undeof organisms are slices of evolutionary histories, a visitor from the mid- to late 19th century might be utterly puzzled that evolutionary and developmental studies were conceived us a separate disciplines in the first place. But history may have much more work to do here. As Alan Love has begun to show us, the story of the  exclusion of embryology/developmental biology from the synthesis is only part of the answer to the question of why philosophical work needs to be done toward integrating evolutionary and developmental studies. An equally significant  exclusion relates to another puzzling feature of the current revival of interest in development the renewed interest in the biological investigation of form functional morphology. In some writers who created, and now defend, the neo-Darwinian synthesis, neo-Darwinism is virtually synonymous with the rejection of morphology which they associate with essentialism, typology, and sometimes with German idealism.  Population thinking is the key to the triumph of Darwinism, and it swept away morphology. Well, perhaps& but Charles Darwin didn t see it that way. 28 ^hhhhoqjvNxxxxz| $r $d$d$dhhnnvqzqqqqdvhvjvxxxzz|| "$lpr0JmHH*6 In the Origin, recall, he closes his discussion of difficulties for his theory with a paragraph on those  two great laws governing the formation of organism: Unity of Type and Conditions of Existence. By unity of type is meant that fundamental agreemen<Origin p. 434>29